Results for 'Elgin S. Moyer'

982 found
Order:
  1. Great Leaders of the Christian Church.Elgin S. Moyer - 1952
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  31
    Herodotus and an Egyptian mirage: the genealogies of the Theban priests.Ian S. Moyer - 2002 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 122:70-90.
    This article re-evaluates the significance attributed to Hecataeus¿ encounter with the Theban priests described by Herodotus (2.143) by setting it against the evidence of Late Period Egyptian representations of the past. In the first part a critique is offered of various approaches Classicists have taken to this episode and its impact on Greek historiography. Classicists have generally imagined this as an encounter in which the young, dynamic and creative Greeks construct an image of the static, ossified and incredibly old culture (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  17
    Determinants of reaction time for digit inequality judgments.R. S. Moyer & T. K. Landauer - 1973 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 1 (3):167-168.
  4. Justice with Michael Sandel.Michael J. Sandel, Bill D. Moyers, Gail Pellett, P. B. S. Video & Public Affairs Television - 1990 - Pbs Video [Distributor].
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Hope for the Long Run with Cornel West.Bill D. Moyers, Cornel West, Public Affairs Television & P. B. S. Video - 1990 - Pbs Video.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  12
    The Gift of the Nile. Hellenizing Egypt from Aeschylus to Alexander (Book).Ian S. Moyer - 2003 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 123:224-225.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  72
    Why the (gene) counting argument fails in the massive modularity debate: The need for understanding gene concepts and genotype-phenotype relationships.Kathryn S. Plaisance, Thomas A. C. Reydon & Mehmet Elgin - 2012 - Philosophical Psychology 25 (6):873-892.
    A number of debates in philosophy of biology and psychology, as well as in their respective sciences, hinge on particular views about the relationship between genotypes and phenotypes. One such view is that the genotype-phenotype relationship is relatively straightforward, in the sense that a genome contains the ?genes for? the various traits that an organism exhibits. This leads to the assumption that if a particular set of traits is posited to be present in an organism, there must be a corresponding (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  14
    Everyday Writing in the Graeco-Roman East. By Roger S. Bagnall. [REVIEW]Ian S. Moyer - 2021 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 134 (3):523-525.
    Everyday Writing in the Graeco-Roman East. By Roger S. Bagnall. Sather Classical Lectures, vol. 69. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 2011. Pp. xiv + 179, illus. $49.95.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  41
    Elgin’s community-oriented steadfastness.Klaas J. Kraay - 2019 - Synthese 198 (6):4985-5008.
    In recent years, epistemologists have devoted enormous attention to this question: what should happen when two epistemic peers disagree about the truth-value of some proposition? Some have argued that that in all such cases, both parties are rationally required to revise their position in some way. Others have maintained that, in at least some cases, neither party is rationally required to revise her position. In this paper, I examine a provocative and under-appreciated argument for the latter view due to (...) Disagreement, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 53–68, 2010; The Philosopher’s Magazine, fourth quarter, pp 77–82, 2012; True enough, MIT Press, Cambridge, 2017; in: Johnson Voicing dissent: the ethics and epistemology of making disagreement public, Routledge, New York, pp 10–21, 2018). I defend it against a series of objections, and I then identify some fruitful ways in which her view could be developed further. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  7
    Robert Hooke's Ambiguous Presentation of "Hooke's Law".Albert Moyer - 1977 - Isis 68:266-275.
  11.  18
    Why Kant and Ecofeminism Don't Mix.Jeanna Moyer - 2001 - Hypatia 16 (3):79-97.
    This paper consists of two sections. In section one, I explore Val Plumwood's description of the features of normative dualism, and briefly discuss how these features are manifest in Immanuel Kant's view of nature. In section two, I evaluate the claims of Holly L. Wilson, who argues that Kant is not a normative dualist. Against Wilson, I will argue that Kant maintains normative dualisms between humans/nature, humans/animals, humans I culture, and men/women. As such, Kant's philosophy is antithetical to the aims (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  21
    Richard Foley's Intellectual Trust in Oneself and Others[REVIEW]Catherine Z. Elgin - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (3):724-734.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  13. Why Kant and ecofeminism don't mix.Jeanna Moyer - 2001 - Hypatia 16 (3):79-97.
    : This paper consists of two sections. In section one, I explore Val Plumwood's description of the features of normative dualism, and briefly discuss how these features are manifest in Immanuel Kant's view of nature. In section two, I evaluate the claims of Holly L. Wilson, who argues that Kant is not a normative dualist. Against Wilson, I will argue that Kant maintains normative dualisms between humans/nature, humans/animals, humans/culture, and men/women. As such, Kant's philosophy is antithetical to the aims of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  13
    Nominalism, constructivism, and relativism in the work of Nelson Goodman.Catherine Z. Elgin (ed.) - 1997 - New York: Garland.
    A challenger of traditions and boundaries A pivotal figure in 20th-century philosophy, Nelson Goodman has made seminal contributions to metaphysics, epistemology, aesthetics, and the philosophy of language, with surprising connections that cut across traditional boundaries. In the early 1950s, Goodman, Quine, and White published a series of papers that threatened to torpedo fundamental assumptions of traditional philosophy. They advocated repudiating analyticity, necessity, and prior assumptions. Some philosophers, realizing the seismic effects repudiation would cause, argued that philosophy should retain the familiar (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  28
    Considered Judgment.Catherine Z. Elgin - 1999 - Princeton University Press.
    Philosophy long sought to set knowledge on a firm foundation, through derivation of indubitable truths by infallible rules. For want of such truths and rules, the enterprise foundered. Nevertheless, foundationalism's heirs continue their forbears' quest, seeking security against epistemic misfortune, while their detractors typically espouse unbridled coherentism or facile relativism. Maintaining that neither stance is tenable, Catherine Elgin devises a via media between the absolute and the arbitrary, reconceiving the nature, goals, and methods of epistemology. In Considered Judgment, she (...)
    No categories
  16.  12
    Take If from Me: The Epistemological Status of Testimony.Catherinez Elgin - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2):291-308.
    Testimony consists in imparting information without supplying evidence or argument to back one's claims. To what extent does testimony convey epistemic warrant? C. J. A. Coady argues, on Davidsonian grounds, that (1) most testimony is true, hence (2) most testimony supplies warrant sufficient for knowledge. I appeal to Grice's maxims to undermine Coady's argument and to show that the matter is more complicated and context‐sensitive than is standardly rocognized. Informative exchanges take place within networks of shared, tacit assumptions that affect (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  17. Take it from me: The epistemological status of testimony.Catherinez Elgin - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2):291-308.
    Testimony consists in imparting information without supplying evidence or argument to back one's claims. To what extent does testimony convey epistemic warrant? C. J. A. Coady argues, on Davidsonian grounds, that (1) most testimony is true, hence (2) most testimony supplies warrant sufficient for knowledge. I appeal to Grice's maxims to undermine Coady's argument and to show that the matter is more complicated and context-sensitive than is standardly recognized. Informative exchanges take place within networks of shared, tacit assumptions that affect (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  18.  36
    Take If from Me: The Epistemological Status of Testimony.Catherinez Elgin - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2):291-308.
    Testimony consists in imparting information without supplying evidence or argument to back one's claims. To what extent does testimony convey epistemic warrant? C. J. A. Coady argues, on Davidsonian grounds, that (1) most testimony is true, hence (2) most testimony supplies warrant sufficient for knowledge. I appeal to Grice's maxims to undermine Coady's argument and to show that the matter is more complicated and context‐sensitive than is standardly rocognized. Informative exchanges take place within networks of shared, tacit assumptions that affect (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  19.  99
    Popper’s Shifting Appraisal of Evolutionary Theory.Elliott Sober & Mehmet Elgin - 2017 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 7 (1):31-55.
    Karl Popper argued in 1974 that evolutionary theory contains no testable laws and is therefore a metaphysical research program. Four years later, he said that he had changed his mind. Here we seek to understand Popper’s initial position and his subsequent retraction. We argue, contrary to Popper’s own assessment, that he did not change his mind at all about the substance of his original claim. We also explore how Popper’s views have ramifications for contemporary discussion of the nature of laws (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  6
    Take It from Me: The Epistemological Status of Testimony.Catherinez Elgin - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2):291-308.
    Testimony consists in imparting information without supplying evidence or argument to back one’s claims. To what extent does testimony convey epistemic warrant? C. J. A. Coady argues, on Davidsonian grounds, that most testimony is true, hence most testimony supplies warrant sufficient for knowledge. I appeal to Grice’s maxims to undermine Coady’s argument and to show that the matter is more complicated and context-sensitive than is standardly recognized. Informative exchanges take place within networks of shared, tacit assumptions that affect the scope (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  21.  27
    Richard Foley's Intellectual Trust in Oneself and Others[REVIEW]Catherine Z. Elgin - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (3):724-734.
    Descartes’ demon is a crafty little devil. Despite centuries of effort by exceedingly clever thinkers, he continues to elude our clutches. Skepticism endures. The reason, Richard Foley thinks, is not hard to discover. It is simply impossible to break through the Cartesian circle. Our only means of vindicating a claim to knowledge or rational belief is to show that it is produced or sustained by our best epistemic methods, that it satisfies the best standards we can devise for rational belief. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22. A survival guide to fission.Mark Moyer - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 141 (3):299 - 322.
    The fission of a person involves what common sense describes as a single person surviving as two distinct people. Thus, say most metaphysicians, this paradox shows us that common sense is inconsistent with the transitivity of identity. Lewis’s theory of overlapping persons, buttressed with tensed identity, gives us one way to reconcile the common sense claims. Lewis’s account, however, implausibly says that reference to a person about to undergo fission is ambiguous. A better way to reconcile the claims of common (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  23.  36
    Epistemology’s Ends, Pedagogy’s Prospects.Catherine Z. Elgin - 1999 - Facta Philosophica 1 (1):39-54.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  24.  12
    With Reference to Reference.Catherine Z. Elgin - 1983 - Hackett Publishing Company.
    "Systematizes and develops in a comprehensive study Nelson Goodman's philosophy of language. The Goodman-Elgin point of view is important and sophisticated, and deals with a number of issues, such as metaphor, ignored by most other theories." --John R. Perry, Stanford University.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  25.  1
    Book Review: Inhabiting the Cruciform God: Kenosis, Justification, and Theosis in Paul's Narrative Soteriology. [REVIEW]Moyer V. Hubbard - 2010 - Journal of Spiritual Formation and Soul Care 3 (1):111-113.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  6
    Book Review: Living in Union with Christ: Paul’s Gospel and Christian Moral Identity. [REVIEW]Moyer Hubbard - 2020 - Journal of Spiritual Formation and Soul Care 13 (2):315-318.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  9
    Elgin's Mission to China and Japan.Matthew V. Lamberti & Laurence Oliphant - 1971 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 91 (4):526.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  56
    Scheffler's symbols.Catherine Z. Elgin - 1993 - Synthese 94 (1):3 - 12.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  29. The legacy of Nelson Goodman.Catherine Z. Elgin - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (3):679-690.
    Nelson Goodman was one of the soaring figures of twentieth century philosophy. His work radically reshaped the subject, forcing fundamental reconceptions of philosophy’s problems, ends, and means. Goodman not only contributed to diverse fields, from philosophy of language to aesthetics, from philosophy of science to mereology, his works cut across these and other fields, revealing shared features and connecting links that narrowly focused philosophers overlook. That the author of The Structure of Appearance also wrote Languages of Art is not in (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30. Goodman's Rigorous Relativism.Catherine Z. Elgin - 1984 - Journal of Thought 19 (4):36-45.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  55
    Indeterminacy, underdetermination, and the anomalism of the mental.C. Z. Elgin - 1980 - Synthese 45 (2):233 - 255.
    Davidson's token-Token identity theory is based on the indeterminacy of translation. I argue that psychological theories, Like other theories, Are underdetermined by the evidence, And that their reduction, Like other reductions, Is subject to the indeterminacy of translation. This does not invalidate reduction, But it does raise epistemic difficulties. Accepting a claim as law-Like involves uncertainty and risk. There are ideological reasons for thinking that psychophysical reduction involves risks we should not take.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Interpretation and Identity: Can the Work Survive the World?Nelson Goodman & Catherine Z. Elgin - 1986 - Critical Inquiry 12 (3):564-575.
    Predictions concerning the end of the world have proven less reliable than your broker’s recommendations or your fondest hopes. Whether you await the end fearfully or eagerly, you may rest assured that it will never come—not because the world is everlasting but because it has already ended, if indeed it ever began. But we need not mourn, for the world is indeed well lost, and with it the stultifying stereotypes of absolutism: the absurd notions of science as the effort to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33.  5
    Understanding’s Tethers.Catherine Z. Elgin - 2007 - In Christoph Jäger & Winfried Löffler (eds.), Epistemology: Contexts, Values, Disagreement. Papers of the 34th International Ludwig Wittgenstein-Symposium in Kirchberg, 2011. The Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society. pp. 131-146.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34.  14
    Philosophical Inquiry: Classic and Contemporary Readings.Jonathan Eric Adler & Catherine Z. Elgin (eds.) - 2007 - Hackett Publishing Company.
    This meticulously edited anthology provides a comprehensive, problems-oriented entree to philosophy. Substantial readings from major classical and contemporary thinkers--featuring many of Hackett's widely acclaimed translations--are supported by a general introduction, engaging introductions to each major topic, and a glossary of important philosophical terms.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Fiction as Thought Experiment.Catherine Z. Elgin - 2014 - Perspectives on Science 22 (2):221-241.
    Jonathan Bennett (1974) maintains that Huckleberry Finn’s deliberations about whether to return Jim to slavery afford insight into the tension between sympathy and moral judgment; Miranda Fricker (2007) argues that the trial scene in To Kill a Mockingbird affords insight into the nature of testimonial injustice. Neither claims merely that the works prompt an attentive reader to think something new or to change her mind. Rather, they consider the reader cognitively better off for her encounters with the novels. Nor is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  36.  59
    Between the absolute and the arbitrary.Catherine Z. Elgin - 1997 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    In Between the Absolute and the Arbitrary, Catherine Z. Elgin maps a constructivist alternative to the standard Anglo-American conception of philosophy's ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  37.  27
    Robert Hooke's Ambiguous Presentation of "Hooke's Law".Albert E. Moyer - 1977 - Isis 68 (2):266-275.
  38. Relocating aesthetics: Goodman's epistemic turn.Catherine Z. Elgin - 1993 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 46 (185):171-186.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39. Cartwright on explanation and idealization.Mehmet Elgin & Elliott Sober - 2002 - Erkenntnis 57 (3):441 - 450.
    Nancy Cartwright (1983, 1999) argues that (1) the fundamental laws of physics are true when and only when appropriate ceteris paribus modifiers are attached and that (2) ceteris paribus modifiers describe conditions that are almost never satisfied. She concludes that when the fundamental laws of physics are true, they don't apply in the real world, but only in highly idealized counterfactual situations. In this paper, we argue that (1) and (2) together with an assumption about contraposition entail the opposite conclusion (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  40.  51
    Nelson Goodman's new riddle of induction.Catherine Z. Elgin (ed.) - 1997 - New York: Garland.
    A challenger of traditions and boundaries A pivotal figure in 20th-century philosophy, Nelson Goodman has made seminal contributions to metaphysics, epistemology, aesthetics, and the philosophy of language, with surprising connections that cut across traditional boundaries. In the early 1950s, Goodman, Quine, and White published a series of papers that threatened to torpedo fundamental assumptions of traditional philosophy. They advocated repudiating analyticity, necessity, and prior assumptions. Some philosophers, realizing the seismic effects repudiation would cause, argued that philosophy should retain the familiar (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  36
    Nelson Goodman's philosophy of art.Catherine Z. Elgin (ed.) - 1997 - New York: Garland.
    A challenger of traditions and boundaries A pivotal figure in 20th-century philosophy, Nelson Goodman has made seminal contributions to metaphysics, epistemology, aesthetics, and the philosophy of language, with surprising connections that cut across traditional boundaries. In the early 1950s, Goodman, Quine, and White published a series of papers that threatened to torpedo fundamental assumptions of traditional philosophy. They advocated repudiating analyticity, necessity, and prior assumptions. Some philosophers, realizing the seismic effects repudiation would cause, argued that philosophy should retain the familiar (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  80
    Nelson Goodman's theory of symbols and its applications.Catherine Z. Elgin (ed.) - 1997 - New York: Garland.
    A challenger of traditions and boundaries A pivotal figure in 20th-century philosophy, Nelson Goodman has made seminal contributions to metaphysics, epistemology, aesthetics, and the philosophy of language, with surprising connections that cut across traditional boundaries. In the early 1950s, Goodman, Quine, and White published a series of papers that threatened to torpedo fundamental assumptions of traditional philosophy. They advocated repudiating analyticity, necessity, and prior assumptions. Some philosophers, realizing the seismic effects repudiation would cause, argued that philosophy should retain the familiar (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  77
    Quine's double standard: Indeterminacy and quantifying in.Catherine Z. Elgin - 1979 - Synthese 42 (3):353 - 377.
  44.  15
    Project Y: The Los Alamos Story. David S. Hawkins, Edith Truslow, Ralph Carlisle Smith.Albert E. Moyer - 1984 - Isis 75 (3):627-628.
  45. Understanding: Art and Science.Catherine Z. Elgin - 1993 - Synthese 95 (1):13-28.
    The arts and the sciences perform many of the same cognitive functions, both serving to advance understanding. This paper explores some of the ways exemplification operates in the two fields. Both scientific experiments and works of art highlight, underscore, display, or convey some of their own features. They thereby focus attention on them, and make them available for examination and projection. Thus, the Michelson-Morley experiment exemplifies the constancy of the speed of light. Jackson Pollock's "Number One" exemplifies the viscosity of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  46. Statues and Lumps: A Strange Coincidence?Mark Moyer - 2006 - Synthese 148 (2):401-423.
    Puzzles about persistence and change through time, i.e., about identity across time, have foundered on confusion about what it is for ‘two things’ to be have ‘the same thing’ at a time. This is most directly seen in the dispute over whether material objects can occupy exactly the same place at the same time. This paper defends the possibility of such coincidence against several arguments to the contrary. Distinguishing a temporally relative from an absolute sense of ‘the same’, we see (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  47. The Function of Knowledge.Catherine Z. Elgin - 2021 - Analysis 81 (1):100-107.
    Human beings are epistemically interdependent. Much of what we know and much of what we need to know we glean from others. Being a gregarious bunch, we are prone to venturing opinions whether they are warranted or not. This makes information transfer a tricky business. What we want from others is not just information, but reliable information. When we seek information, we are in the position of enquirers not examiners. We ask someone whether p because we do not ourselves already (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  48.  33
    Knowledge is closed under analytic content.Samuel Z. Elgin - 2021 - Synthese 199 (1-2):5339-5353.
    I am concerned with epistemic closure—the phenomenon in which some knowledge requires other knowledge. In particular, I defend a version of the closure principle in terms of analyticity; if an agent S knows that p is true and that q is an analytic part of p, then S knows that q. After targeting the relevant notion of analyticity, I argue that this principle accommodates intuitive cases and possesses the theoretical resources to avoid the preface paradox.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  49.  13
    Promise ahead: a vision of hope and action for humanity's future.Duane Elgin - 2000 - New York: W. Morrow.
    Outlines four emerging "opportunity trends," including voluntary simplicity, that readers can utilize to surmount social, economic, and environmental challenges ...
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Knowledge is Closed Under Analytic Content.Samuel Elgin - manuscript
    I am concerned with epistemic closure—the phenomenon in which some knowledge requires other knowledge. In particular, I defend a version of the closure principle in terms of analyticity; if an agent S knows that p is true, then S knows that all analytic parts of p are true as well. After targeting the relevant notion of analyticity, I argue that this principle accommodates intuitive cases and possesses the theoretical resources to avoid the preface paradox. I close by arguing that contextualists (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 982